Can Social Justice Be Justified ?
Glen Beck once told his listeners
that if their church teaches social justice, they should leave that church.
Beck walked his talk by leaving the Catholic Church
The mention of social justice,
sometimes called economic justice, arouses controversy, not only in terms of what
is right and wrong, but even in terms of what the concept means. Some deny that
the concept has any meaning. Another
name for social justice, “distributive justice,” evokes the question of how the
material goods of the world should be distributed. The views on this issue vary
from those who argue that the current situation is radically unfair and that
redistribution is a moral imperative, to those who argue that the whole notion
of social justice is fraudulent and that no one has the right to distribute
anything except his or her own property. A representative expression of the
dismissal of social justice by some
conservatives is found in a column by economist Thomas Sowell: “What does
‘economic justice’ mean except that you want something that someone else
produced, without having to produce anything yourself in return?”
Is the present system just? When
offered to a class of college students, or to a group of adults, my experience
shows that this question can produce a lot of heat and unproductive opinions
unless we can achieve some clarity on the meaning of justice. Some assume that
justice means equality and point out that the current situation is patently
unjust. Opponents of social justice agree that social justice means equality,
and so they reject the notion of social justice as a theft against those who
have earned wealth. Also, those who reject social justice often depict it as a
disguise to increase the power of government.
The whole notion of social justice
requires clarification. Justice generally means the right distribution of
benefits and burdens. Differences abound on the question of what constitutes
“right distribution” As a step toward clarification we can express the notion
of justice as follows: “Every person
should get what he or she deserves. No one in a society should be arbitrarily
deprived of its benefits nor arbitrarily made to carry its burdens.” The
question remains as to what benefits and burdens, if any, belong to an
individual simply by being a member of a society. Clearly, we do not all
receive equal benefits or carry equal burdens. This fact of inequality does not
necessarily constitute injustice, but it provides an opening into a better
understanding. Taking factual inequality as a starting point, we ask whether
any reasons justify the unequal distribution of benefits and burdens.
Capitalism and Justice
Some defenders of capitalism argue
that the inequalities brought about by a free market, are justified by the fact
that those who receive more are precisely those who contribute more as judged
by the market. A Capitalist view of justice, playing on the Marxian principle
of “From each according to his ability, to each according to his need,” states,
"From each according to his willingness to participate in the system; to
each according to his success in participating.” In capitalism, the principle
is not simply “from each according to his or her ability,” but from each
according to his or her ability and
willingness to contribute. The willingness consists not only of a general
willingness to work, but to do a particular kind of work, or develop a
particular kind of skill, or a particular entrepreneurial idea. For example,
one person might learn a construction trade such as brick-laying or carpentry
and wish to work in construction; another may want to start a small business
such a restaurant; a third might want to work in management for a
corporation. If these each achieve what
they set out to do, they will receive a wage, profit, or salary, and the
economy will benefit from their particular skill and work. Anyone may fail
because of lack of ability or because their skills are not needed at a given
time. In the example above, a business recession may lead to a loss of
livelihood for all three. According to the capitalist or free-market theorist,
such a loss is a misfortune but not an injustice.
The terms “capitalist” and
“libertarian” often overlap and sometimes are used interchangeably. Libertarians
generally believe that individual freedom should be maximized and that
government activity should be limited to the military and police work of
preventing force and fraud. Of course, not all capitalists are libertarians,
nor do they necessarily reject the notion of using public funds to help people
in need. While the libertarians reject the notion of social justice, capitalists
may defend the value of social justice but affirm that the free market is the
most just distributor of wealth. They base their arguments on the fact that a
person’s ability and willingness to work create wealth not only for that
person, but for the whole society. The successful capitalists, while becoming
rich, also provide jobs, products, and tax revenue. Without the activity of the
capitalist, everyone would be less well-off, including those who are relatively
poor.
A Reasonable Approach to Economic Justice
Given the libertarian argument that
no one has the right to distribute any property other than his or her own, and
given the capitalist argument that the market can distribute goods more justly
than any other human mechanism, is there a need for a separate category of
social justice? In fact there are two moral principles that create a mandate
for clear thinking on social justice. These principles are the notion that the goods of the earth belong to all,
and the notion of moral equality,
meaning that every human being has the right to be treated with respect. Merely
stating these principles does not necessarily disprove the argument that a free
market provides the best distribution, nor does it prove that any existing
inequalities are unjust. But the principles do require us to examine what
constitutes social justice and to work toward its implementation.
One of the strongest arguments for
social justice, if not for equality, stems from the notion that the goods of
the earth belong to all. This argument did not arise in pre-modern times when
the land was thought to belong to the king, or to a feudal strongman who was literally
a land lord. This notion changed drastically with the Enlightenment when
thinkers such as John Locke argued that things in their natural state belonged
to all. But he laid down the basis for private property by arguing that things
have value only when mixed with human labor. Since the work of our hands is
ours individually, the product of that work is also ours as private property.
This principle established both the basis for justice and the approval of
inequality. Inequalities result from some persons working more effectively than
others thus creating more value. But the inequalities have to be justified
since the goods begin by belonging equally to all.
A second Enlightenment idea that
leads to a notion of social justice is the moral equality of all human beings.
In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the notion of equality referred to
moral, political, and legal equality, but not to economic equality. But if we
are by nature equal as human beings, some justification must be given if economic
inequality is to be morally acceptable and not merely a result of the more powerful grabbing more than they
deserve. While few people today argue for a simple equality, we differ widely
among ourselves as to how much inequality can be tolerated, and on what
grounds. The libertarians argue that any inequality is justified as long as
there is no force or fraud involved.
I contend, to the contrary, that there
is a place for public policy that can rightly be called social justice. Although
problems that can be solved by individuals and communities should not be taken
over by government, nevertheless there are some problems that can be dealt with
only in the public sphere. We can discern injustice
in the structures and laws of society, and therefore we can define what constitutes
social justice. Some of the more
obvious historical examples of social injustice include slavery and
discrimination. But others examples include omissions, such as the failure on
the part of the public sector to protect individuals from the results of
environmental destruction, dangerous or exploitative working conditions, and
inferior educational opportunities.
Any person’s concept of justice is
based on his or her concept of what a
human being is and why we should be concerned with treating each person
justly. The view of the human person presented in this blog maintains that our capacity for membership in
any genuine community rests on the fact that we are rational, free, capable and
in need of meaningful work, communal, and needing the opportunity to realize
our full physical, intellectual, emotional, and spiritual capacity. Therefore
any structure or practice that inhibits a person from realizing his or her
human nature is unjust, and that which promotes it is just. Justice as a moral
task can mean doing whatever we can to assure that each person has an
opportunity to realize his or her human potential. This entails much more than
removal of obstacles such as discrimination.
Real equality of opportunity must include providing the conditions that
make realization possible. If a person has the ability and desire to develop
productive skills, but lacks the opportunity, does this constitute an
injustice? The role of justice lies in determining what each person has the
right to and who has the obligation to provide it.
Integrity and Integration in the Economy
The key to understanding social
justice consists in recognizing that we are mutually interdependent. Each of
our lives has an impact on countless people of whom we are not aware, and the
activities of other people impact each of us. No one in isolation and relying
on only his or her own native ability can become an engineer, an accountant, a
steamfitter, a golfer, or a musician. All of these things require physical and
social structures and involve imitation and intense education, both formal and
informal. While those who deny social justice may agree that we have an
obligation as individuals to people whom we immediately affect, our universal
mutual interdependence requires us to also pay attention to how we collectively
impact other people through our political, economic, educational, and civil
institutions.
Any society that excludes some part
of the population either by design or by neglect, to that extent suffers a
deficiency of justice. Although giving a person a handout, by the state or by
private charity, beats letting the person starve or freeze, such largess falls
short of justice. The goal of achieving a just society requires that we,
individually and collectively, do what we can to assure that each person can
take a productive social and economic role.
To achieve this level of inclusiveness would be very difficult if not
practically impossible. Nevertheless it is a standard against which we can
measure our level of success and failure at building a just society.
The theme
of this blog is purposive integration or “teleological harmony.” We can rate
our society as a just society to the extent that each and every individual has
a place in the society that enables them to develop their full human potential.
There will probably always be misfits, sociopaths, and criminals. The question
of social justice requires that we ask whether we are giving each person a
chance to be productive and prosperous, and how we treat those who reject or
neglect the opportunities that are provided. Whether their problem is physical,
psychological or moral, they still belong to the human community. We can move
to seek ways to incorporate them although there is no guarantee of
success. Or we can reject or neglect
them with the self-assurance that their problem is their fault not ours. As in
every aspect of ethics, we can integrate or disintegrate
No comments:
Post a Comment