Is Free Will an Illusion?
The issue of free
will is closely linked to the meaning of consciousness because the whole
question of free will asks whether consciousness can determine matter without
being completely determined by matter. Put more specifically, can the conscious
subject decide on particular brain events without the decision having been
predetermined by other brain events? For example, consider a person who
resolves to improve his or her fitness by taking up running. It seems, from the
person‘s point of view, that the resolution causes the mind to focus on health
and fitness so that physical changes takes place. The person now devotes time
and energy to running on a road or track, time that would otherwise have been
spent on some sedentary activity such as playing with a computer. But was the
origin and continuation of the resolution caused by some other physical brain
event of which the person had neither awareness nor control? Here I will resume
the dialogue with Christof Koch’s Consciousness.
Koch offers as a
definition of free will: “You are free if, under identical circumstances, you
could have acted otherwise. Identical circumstances refer to not only the same
external conditions but also the same brain states” (Koch, 92). He considers
debates on the reality of free will to be futile since we cannot go back and do
things differently. I think that his observation about the futility of debates
on free will stems from his definition rather than on the real possibility of
free will. His definition looks backward, “Could you have acted differently?”
This definition sets up a sure failure for free will since, to the best of my
knowledge, no free will theory would say that we are free to change the past.
What’s done is done. But free will takes on a different meaning when we apply
it to the future. The question of free will can be restated as: “Can I, through
‘attention with effort,’ make my future different from what it would be without
such effort.” The phrase, “attention with effort,” flows from William James and
his notion that ideas control action and that through effort we can determine
which ideas control our action. This understanding need not slip into futility
since it has a real impact. Suppose a young person heard this idea from someone
whom she respects and tries to apply it to her life. Would this notion not make
a difference in the way she lived? The practical significance of this question
can best be understood by reviewing William James’s description of free will.
According to
James, every idea has some bodily expression and ideas either instigate or
inhibit muscular movements. Since we generally have several ideas at any one
time, some contradicting others, we act on the most dominant one. We are free
if and only if we can, by effort, make a chosen idea dominant by deliberately
attending to it.
For example, a
person who has a plate of fried chicken in front of him may eat it without
effort since the dominant idea is how good it tastes. But if the same person
turns his attention to the desirability of clean arteries and a healthy body
weight, he may, through effort, make this healthy image dominant and so change
his eating habits. The whole question of free will comes down to whether “we,”
our conscious selves, can determine the ideas that we attend to and the amount
of effort that we can exert to maintain the attention.
If
the materialists are right, then the whole process of “attention with effort”
originates in molecules of which we may not be consciously aware, and “we” are
mere spectators of a process over which we have no control. We cannot prove
that the materialists are right or wrong, However, it is reasonable to believe
that we can, perhaps to a very small degree, choose what we think is good, pay
attention to it with effort, and thereby make our lives different from what
they otherwise would be. If this assumption is true, then we have a free will
and consciousness has a degree of control over matter.
Koch
offers two reasons to doubt that consciousness can exert control over matter.
The first reason is based on the conservation of energy. Anything that happens
in the physical world depends on the existing energy. Nothing happens without
using some amount of energy that constitutes the physical universe. So the
neural correlates of thought, the physical conditions necessary for any
thought, depend on some physical event. They cannot originate from any
non-physical entity, even if there are non-physical entities.
Koch
leaves an infinitesimal crack in the closed neuro-physical system that may
provide an opportunity for free will, but he considers the degree of freedom to
be insignificant, and on a practical level, indistinguishable from mere chance.
In describing the one opportunity for free will, Koch refers to the view of
Karl Popper and John Eccles, advocates of free will, that “the conscious mind
imposes its will onto the brain by manipulating the way neurons communicate
with each other in the regions of the cortex concerned with the planning of
movement.” According to the Popper-Eccles view, the mind need not supply the
physical energy for the movement of the chemical signals, but it can “direct
traffic” by promoting activity in theses neurons and preventing it in those.
But Koch argues that such influence is possible only in quantum-mechanical
states in which there is a certain probability that a synapse will or will not
switch. According to his argument, the mind cannot change the probability, but
it might determine what will happen on any given event. Control over a single
event does not change the probability that the person will act this way rather
than that way. But, we may ask, if the mind can control this one event, might
it also influence the next one and the one after? Could this type of influence,
over time, not change the probability?
Koch
follows up with further arguments against the feasibility of free will (Koch
105-105). He cites and describes experimental evidence that brain activity that
instigates an apparent act of will, actually begins before the actor is aware
of making a decision. In Koch’s example, a person indicates the instant that he
or she decides to move an arm. The actual movement of the arm coincides with
the moment of their awareness, but EEG information shows that the process has
started prior to the decision. This experiment implies that what we feel is a
free choice is, in fact, the result of brain activity of which we are unaware.
However,
free will is not about a single action but about a life-time of habit
formation. In the case of the arm movement experiment, it might be just as well
if unconscious neuro-physical events choose the moment to move an arm. But
there are many human activities in which it is crucial to choose a particular
act at just the right moment. Such examples abound especially in sports. For
example, if a baseball player is deciding to steal second base, he must pick
the right moment. If he leaves a second too early he might get picked off; a
second too late and he will be thrown out. So an unconscious physical brain
event, which occurs before the actual steal attempt, might serve him better
than slower conscious deliberation. But a baseball player has spent a lot of
time deliberately developing the habit of running bases. He has chosen to
develop these habits, therefore he has chosen the neural pathways that enable
him to seize the moment without deliberation. The deliberate development of
habits applies to all sports, music, dancing, cooking, hunting, and many other
activities. We may freely choose to spend time developing these skills. When
time sensitivity is not an issue, we are free to the extent that, over time we
can choose how we develop our habitual behavior. The habits serve us well when
we must act “in the blink of an eye.” While the above description does not
“prove” free will, it does provide a feasible belief in free will that survives
Koch’s argument against it.
A
further look at Koch reveals that he himself believes in free will. He affirms
a "compatibilist” notion of free will, which means that you are free if
and only if you can follow your own desires and preferences. For example,
smokers who wish to stop smoking are free or not free depending on whether they
are able to follow their desire to stop. Some can and some can’t. But even in
the case of those who successfully follow their desire, the desires themselves
stem from biological and psychological events over which the person has no
authorship. (93). The person who wishes to smoke would be free if he were
allowed to smoke without limitations and prohibitions. The same holds true of
those who wish to express their preference for unlimited acquisitions, sexual
encounters, or physical expression of anger. In Koch’s case, he not only wants
to be able to express his desires and preferences without coercion or
prohibition, but also specifies what he wants his desires to be. (I assume that
this is also true of Dennett and most other materialists in spite of their
theory).
It
is worth quoting Koch at length to show his position regarding free will.
After rejecting both classical
determinism that sees the future as already fixed, and also rejecting the
notion that an immaterial “soul” can influence matter, he concludes:
“I’ve taken two
lessons from these insights. First, I‘ve adopted a more pragmatic compatibilist
conception of free will. I strive to
live as free of external and internal constraints as possible. The only
exception should be constraints that I deliberately
and consciously impose upon my self, chief among them constraints motivated
by ethical concerns; whatever you do, do not hurt others and try to leave the planet a better place
than you found it. Other considerations include family, health, financial
stability, and mindfulness. Second, I try
to understand my unconscious motivations, fears, and desires better. I reflect
deeper about my own actions and emotions than my younger self did” (emphases
added).
Who or what is the “I” that
“strives,” “deliberately and consciously imposes,” and “tries?” It seems that
if consciousness has no autonomy, we can only hope that our molecules will do these
things or, depending on the molecules, hope that they don’t. A dogmatic
materialist may argue that Koch has gone soft in the paragraph quoted
above. But, on the contrary, the hopeful
resolute paragraph may simply show the limitation of materialism.
No comments:
Post a Comment